Legal Realism as a Positivistic Theory of Law
DOI :
https://doi.org/10.5347/isonomia.v0i53.452Mots-clés :
positivisme juridique méthodologique, positivisme juridique théorique, positivisme juridique idéologique, réalisme juridiqueRésumé
Le réalisme juridique comme théorie positiviste du droit
Depuis les années 60, en suivant Norberto Bobbio, tout le monde est (ou devrait être) capable de distinguer le positivisme juridique (LP) méthodologique, théorique, et idéologique. D’ailleurs, dans la littérature juridique et philosophique italienne, le LP est souvent opposé au réalisme juridique (LR). Il faut cependant se demander : de quel type de LP et de quel type de LR parle-t-on ? Quant au LR, ceux qui opposent réalisme et positivisme ont surtout à l’esprit le réalisme scandinave, en particulier Olivecrona et Ross. En ce qui concerne le LP, ceux qui opposent réalisme et positivisme ont à l’esprit soit la théorie du droit dominante au XIXe siècle, soit la théorie pure de Kelsen. L’opposition entre le LR et la théorie pure est bien fondée. Néanmoins, une telle opposition ne découle pas d'une prétendue position anti-positiviste du LR. Elle dépend plutôt de deux thèses carrément non positivistes de Kelsen : le concept de validité comme force contraignante et la théorie normative de la science juridique, conçue comme un ensemble d’énoncés déontiques (non factuels) faisant écho aux normes valides (c’est-à-dire contraignantes). L’opposition entre le LR et le LP du XIXe siècle est également solide, mais ne tient pas quand on parle du LP contemporain, qui est principalement conçu comme une attitude méthodologique (Benthamite) envers le droit. Le LR est une vision ouvertement positiviste du droit. Certes, pas tous les juristes positivistes sont réalistes, mais tous les réalistes sont positivistes (‘durs’).
Références
Austin, John, 1879, Lectures on Jurisprudence or The Philosophy of Positive Law, 4th ed. by R. Campbell, John Murray, London.
Baldassarre, Antonio, 2005, “Miseria del positivismo giuridico”, in AA. VV., Studi in onore di Gianni Ferrara, Giappichelli, Torino, 2005, vol. I, 201-216.
Bentham, Jeremy, 1789, An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation, ed. by J.H. Burns and H.L.A. Hart, Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1996.
Bobbio, Norberto, 1961, Il positivismo giuridico, reprinted Giappichelli, Torino, 1966.
____________, 1963, Locke e il diritto naturale, reprinted Giappichelli, Torino, 2017.
____________, 1965, Giusnaturalismo e positivismo giuridico, Comunità, Milano.
____________, 1966, “Intervento”, in Tavola rotonda sul positivismo giuridico, Quaderni della rivista Il politico, Giuffré, Milano, 69-73.
____________, 1970a, “’Sein’ and ‘Sollen’ in Legal Science”, Archivfür Rechts- und Sozialphilosophie, LVI, 7-29.
____________, 1970b, Studi per una teoria generale del diritto, Giappichelli, Torino, new impression 2012.
Bulygin, Eugenio, 2006, El positivismo jurídico, Cátedra Ernesto Garzón Valdés, Fontamara, México.
Carcaterra, Gaetano, 1984, Il principio di normatività. Riflessioni sul normativismo, Bulzoni, Roma.
Chiassoni, Pierluigi, 2012, “Il realismo radicale della teoria pura del diritto”, Materiali per una storia della cultura giuridica, XLII, 237-261.
____________, 2013a, Positivismo giuridico. Una investigazione analitica, Mucchi, Modena.
____________, 2013b, “Wiener Realism”, in Luis Duarte d’Almeida, John Gardner, Leslie Green (eds.), Kelsen Revisited: New Essays on the Pure Theory of Law., Oxford/Hart Publishing, Portland/Oregon, 2013, 131-162.
____________, 2016, El discreto placer del positivismo jurídico, Universidad Externado de Colombia, Bogotá.
Comanducci, Paolo, 2009, “Constitucionalización y neoconstitucionalismo”, in Paolo Comanducci, Marian Ahumada Ruiz, Daniel González Lagier (eds.), Positivismo jurídico y neoconstitucionalismo, Fundación Coloquio Jurídico Europeo, Madrid.
____________, 2010, Hacia una teoría analítica del Derecho. Ensayos escogidos, Centro de Estudios Políticos y Constitucionales, Madrid.
Eng, Svein, 2011, “Lost in the System or Lost in Translation? The Exchanges between Hart and Ross”, Ratio Juris, XXIV, 194-246.
Grzegorczyk, Christophe, Michaut, Françoise, Troper, Michel (eds.), 1992, Le positivisme juridique, L.G.D.J., Paris.
Guastini, Riccardo, 2011, “Rule-Scepticism Restated”, in Leslie Green, Brian Leiter (eds.), Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Law, vol. 1, Oxford U.P., Oxford, 138-161.
Hägerström, Axel, 1953, Inquiries into the Nature of Law and Morals, ed. by K. Olivecrona, Almqvist and Wiksell, Stockholm.
Hart, H.L.A., 1958 "Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals”, Harvard Law Review, Vol. LXXI, 4, 593-629, reprinted in Hart 1983, 49-87.
____________, 1959, “Scandinavian Realism”, reprinted in Hart 1983, 161-169.
____________, 1983, Essays in Jurisprudence and Philosophy, Clarendon, Oxford.
Holtermann, Jakob v. H., 2017, “A Straw Man Revisited: Resettling the Score Between H.L.A. Hart and Scandinavian Legal Realism”, Santa Clara Law Review, 57, 1-42.
Jiménez Cano, Roberto Marino, 2008, Una metateoría del positivismo jurídico, Marcial Pons, Madrid.
Jori, Mario, 1987, Il giuspositivismo analitico italiano prima e dopo la crisi, Giuffré, Milano.
Kelsen, Hans, 1934, Introduction to the Problems of Legal Theory, ed. by Bonnie Litschewski Paulson and Stanley L. Paulson, Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1992.
____________, 1945, General Theory of Law and State, Harvard U. P., Cambridge (Mass.).
____________, 1965, “Law and Logic”, trans. P. Heath, in Hans Kelsen, Essays in Legal and Moral Philosophy, ed. Ota Weinberger, Dordrecht, Reidel, 1973, 228-253.
Leiter, Brian, 2007, Naturalizing Jurisprudence. Essays on American Legal Realism and Naturalism in Legal Philosophy, Oxford U.P., Oxford.
Matteucci, Nicola, 1963, “Positivismo giuridico e costituzionalismo”, Rivista trimestrale di diritto e procedura civile, XVII, 985-1100 (reprinted as a book: Il Mulino, Bologna, 1996).
Millard, Eric, 2008, “Positivisme logique et réalisme juridique”, Analisi e diritto, 177-189.
Modugno, Franco, 2008, Scritti sull’interpretazione costituzionale, ESI, Napoli.
Olivecrona, Karl, 1971, Law as Fact, Stevens & Sons, London.
Pattaro, Enrico, 1966, “Validità o verificabilità del diritto?”, Rivista trimestrale di diritto e procedura civile, 1966, 1005-1056.
____________, 1971, “Il realismo giuridico come alternativa al positivismo giuridico”, Rivista internazionale di filosofia del diritto, I, 61-126.
____________, 1972, “Il positivismo giuridico italiano dalla rinascita alla crisi”, reprinted in Uberto Scarpelli 1976, 451-487.
____________, 1982, “Per una critica della dottrina pura”, in Enrico Pattaro (ed.), Contributi al realismo giuridico, Giuffré, Milano, vol. 1, IX-LXXXVI.
____________, 1984, “La realtà del diritto e la sua conoscenza”, in Antonio Tarantino (ed.), Scienza e politica nel pensiero di Alf Ross, Giuffré, Milano, 103–146.
____________, 2018, “Girovagando… e discutendo”, Materiali per una storia del pensiero giuridico, I, 247-260.
Ross, Alf, 1958, On Law and Justice, Stevens & Sons, London.
____________, 1961, “Validity and the Conflict between Legal Positivism and Natural Law”, reprinted in Stanley L. Paulson and Bonnie Litschewski Paulson (eds.), Normativity and Norms. Critical Perspectives on Kelsenian Themes, Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1998, 147-163.
____________, 1962, “Review of H.L.A. Hart’s The Concept of Law”, The Yale Law Journal, LXXI, 1185-1190.
____________, 1965, Diritto e giustizia, trans. Giacomo Gavazzi, Einaudi, Torino.
____________, 1968, Directives and Norms, Routledge, London.
____________, 1997,Sobre el derecho y la justicia, trad. Genaro R. Carrió, Eudeba, Buenos Aires, 2nd ed.
Ruiz Manero, Juan, 2015, “Bobbio y el positivismo”, Revus, 26, 13-18.
Scarpelli, Uberto, 1965, Cos’è il positivismo giuridico, Comunità, Milano; new impression, ed. by A. Catania and M. Jori, Edizioni scientifiche italiane, Napoli, 1997.
El realismo jurídico como teoría positivista del derecho
Isonomía. Revista de Teoría y Filosofía del Derecho, no. 53, 2020
Instituto Tecnológico Autónomo de México
Riccardo Guastini
guastini@unige.it
Istituto Tarello per la filosofia del diritto - Università degli Studi di Genova, Italia
Esta obra está bajo una Licencia Creative Commons Atribución-NoComercial 4.0 Internacional.
Received: 12 November 2020
Accepted: 19 November 2020
Abstract: Since the Sixties, following Norberto Bobbio, everyone is (or should be) used to distinguish among methodological, theoretical, and ideological legal positivism (LP). By the way, in Italian legal-philosophical literature, LP is often opposed to legal realism (LR). One has to wonder, however: what kind of LP and what kind of LR are we talking about? As to LR, those scholars who oppose realism and positivism have in mind most of all Scandinavian Realism, especially Olivecrona and Ross. As to LP, those scholars who oppose realism and positivism have in mind either the 19th century prevailing theory of law or Kelsen’s pure theory. The opposition between LR and the pure theory is sound. Nonetheless, such an opposition does not arise from a supposed anti-positivistic stance of LR. It depends on two non-positivistic theses endorsed by Kelsen: the concept of validity as binding force, and the normative theory of legal science, conceived of a set of deontic (non-factual) sentences echoing valid (i.e., binding) norms. The opposition between LR and 19th century LP is equally sound, but does not hold when referred to contemporary LP, which is mainly conceived of as a methodological (Benthamite) attitude towards the law. LR is an openly positivistic view about the law. To be sure, not all positivist legal scholars are realist, but all realists are (“hard”) positivists.
Keywords: methodological legal positivism, theoretical legal positivism, ideological legal positivism, legal realism.
Resumen: Desde los años sesenta del siglo XX, siguiendo a Norberto Bobbio, todo el mundo es (o debería ser) capaz de distinguir entre tres formas de positivismo jurídico (LP): (a) metodológico, (b) teórico, y (c) ideológico. Por cierto, en la literatura iusfilosófica italiana, a menudo se contrapone el LP al realismo jurídico (LR). Sin embargo, ¿de qué tipo de LP y de LR estamos hablando? En cuanto al LR, los iusfilósofos que oponen realismo y positivismo tienen en mente esencialmente el realismo escandinavo, especialmente Olivecrona y Ross. En cuanto al LP, aquellos iusfilósofos que oponen realismo y positivismo tienen en mente, o bien la teoría del derecho dominante en el siglo XIX, o bien la teoría pura de Kelsen. La oposición entre el LR y la teoría pura es fundada. No obstante, tal oposición no surge de una supuesta postura anti-positivista del LR. Depende más bien de dos tesis no positivistas sostenidas por Kelsen: el concepto de validez como fuerza vinculante, y la teoría normativa de la ciencia jurídica, concebida como un conjunto de oraciones deónticas (no fácticas) que se hacen eco de normas válidas (es decir, vinculantes). La oposición entre el LR y el LP del siglo XIX es igualmente fundada, pero no tiene sentido cuando referida al LP contemporáneo, que consiste principalmente en una actitud metodológica (“Benthamita”) hacia el derecho. El LR es una visión abiertamente positivista del derecho. Sin duda, no todos los juristas positivistas son realistas, pero todos los realistas son positivistas (“duros”).
Palabras clave: positivismo jurídico metodológico, positivismo jurídico teórico, positivismo jurídico metodológico, realismo jurídico.
I. Legal Positivism Analysed
In 1961, the outstanding Italian legal philosopher Norberto Bobbio introduced an unsurpassed analysis of legal positivism (LP).1 In his view, the phrase “LP” is actually used in juristic literature with different meanings, referring to three different and logically independent doctrines (Bobbio 1961, part II; see also Bobbio 1965, 101 ff.).2
(i) Methodological positivism. In the first place, LP is a methodological attitude, namely a value-free approach to law. The philosophy of (legal) science of LP circumscribes the object of (legal) science to the law as it actually is, excluding any inquiry about the law as it ought to be. Legal cognition is expository, not censorial, jurisprudence.3
In John Austin’s words: «The existence of law is one thing, its merit or demerit is another. Whether it be or be not is one enquiry; whether it be or be not conformable to an assumed standard, is a different enquiry. A law, which actually exists, is a law though we happen to dislike it».4
It should be stressed that, according to Bobbio, this methodological attitude is actually shared by modern legal scholars, who are used to distinguish between jus conditum and jus condendum and consider only jus conditum as the appropriate subject of their inquiry – in other words, in his view, the actual work of legal scholars is a purely descriptive enterprise.5
At any rate, the positivistic value-free approach to law presupposes a criterion of identification of positive law itself – such a criterion is provided by a theory of law, and this is the second face of LP (or LP par excellence).
(ii) Theoretical positivism. In the second place, LP is a theory of law, namely the theory generally shared by 19th century jurists,6 which includes a number of substantive theses, such as the following:
law is the set of commands enacted by a sovereign authority;
the binding force of such commands is guaranteed by the threat of sanctions;
law is a complete and consistent system, in such a way that no gaps and no normative conflicts exist;
legal interpretation is a cognitive enterprise consisting in ascertaining the will of the legislative authority;
the application of law is an eminently logical activity consisting in (ascertaining facts and) inferring individual prescriptions from general rules (“All thieves ought to be punished. X is a thief. Hence X is to be punished”).
(iii) Ideological positivism. In the third place, LP is an ideology, that is a normative stance according to which positive law ought to be obeyed – there is a (moral or political) obligation to obey the law. On the footsteps of Hobbes, justice is identified with positive law.
It should be stressed that ideological positivism, understood this way, is no specified (substantive) normative ethics – rather it is a normative (“formal”) meta-ethics, in the sense that it does not command any definite behaviour, but simply commands to comply with the rules issued by legal authorities (whatever their contents may be). Such an attitude – equal and contrary, so to say, to natural law doctrine, as characterized by Bobbio – is called “ethical legalism” or “ethical formalism”.
To be sure, such three positivistic doctrines, although logically independent, share the “no natural law” thesis – no natural law exists, the only existing “law” (properly understood) being positive law, that is, law “posited” by human norm-creating acts. As Uberto Scarpelli said, laws are not “given” to men, but “made” by them (Scarpelli, 1984, and 1989, 461). The legal character of any entity (a fact, a subject, etc.) depends entirely on its being the object of a legal norm that refers to it (Carcaterra 1984, 5).7
II. The Opposition between LP and Legal Realism
In Italian legal-philosophical literature, LP is often (or even usually) opposed to legal realism.8 One has to wonder, however: what kind of LP and what kind of legal realism are we talking about?
(i) As to legal realism, those scholars who oppose realism and positivism have in mind most of all Scandinavian Realism, especially Olivecrona and Ross (Olivecrona 1971; Ross 1958), completely disregarding American (or Italian, or French) legal realism. This is doubly surprising.
It is true that Olivecrona is a severe critic of LP, but the kind of LP he criticizes is essentially the voluntaristic view about legal norms held by 19th century jurists, such a view being a component of LP understood as a theory of law (in Bobbio’s sense).9 However, Olivecrona, on the tracks of Hägerström,10 definitely shares the methodological side of LP – the view according to which science (in general, including legal science) is a wertfrei empirical enterprise that has to do only with observable phenomena (Olivecrona 1971, 56).
Ross, in turn, is a strong defender of methodological LP – against Kelsen’s concept of validity understood as binding force, that he pictures as a sort of disguised natural law thesis (“quasi-positivism,” Ross 1961), as well as against Hartian “internal point of view” (Ross 1962). Legal science, according to him, is a set of purely descriptive “external” sentences identifying the law in force.11
(ii) As to LP, those scholars who oppose realism and positivism have in mind either the 19th century prevailing theory of law or Kelsen’s pure theory.12
To be sure, the opposition between legal realism and the pure theory is sound. Nonetheless, such an opposition does not arise from a supposed anti-positivistic stance of legal realists. It depends on two non-positivistic theses endorsed by Kelsen: on the one hand, the concept of validity as binding force (Ross 1961); on the other hand, the normative theory of legal science, conceived of a set of deontic (non-factual) sentences echoing valid (i.e., binding) norms (Ross 1958, 38 ff.).
The opposition between legal realism and 19th century LP is equally sound – especially if one takes into account the radically sceptical view of legal realism about interpretation (Guastini 2011) – but does not hold when referred to contemporary LP.
III. Contemporary LP
Nowadays, in the legal philosophy of the 20th and 21th centuries – since Hart (1958) and Bobbio (1961) – LP is mainly conceived of as a methodological attitude towards the law (Bulygin 2006).13 All “classical” positivistic views – as to the very nature of law (viewed as a set of commands backed by the threat of sanctions), the structure of legal systems (assumedly gapless and consistent), and legal interpretation (conceived of as a merely cognitive enterprise) – are by now mostly dismissed.14
The main theses, strictly methodological, of contemporary LP (by the way, shared by Kelsen) are the following.
(i) First, as a matter of course, contemporary positivism denies the existence of so-called natural law (however conceived), assuming law to be a human artefact.15 There are no norms in the very nature of “things” or human relationships – no norm exists without a human act of normative creation. As Kelsen (echoing W. Dubislav) rightly says: “Kein Imperativ ohne Imperator”, that is, no command without anyone commanding (Kelsen 1965). So-called “natural law” is not law properly understood, but (at most) critical morality (Bobbio 1963, 67; 1965, 179 ff.).16 Natural law arises from an evident violation of Hume’s principle – no norms can be (logically) derived from factual statements.17
(ii) Second, LP is a scientific attitude towards the law, grounded on the distinction between expository and censorial jurisprudence – between the law as it actually is and the law as it ought to be (according to some standard of evaluation). Describing the existing law and evaluating it are two different and independent intellectual enterprises. By the way, it is precisely this feature of LP that is currently refused by non-positivist (as well as “soft positivist”) legal scholars – they claim that law cannot even be identified without some kind of moral evaluation.18
(iii) Third, as a consequence of Hume’s principle, no “objective” (moral or political) obligation to obey the law exists – the knowledge of legal norms does not involve any obligation to obey them. To be sure, obedience is what lawmakers demand, but no binding force, no obligation to obey, is conceptually entailed by the very existence or legal validity of a norm. Obedience presupposes not only cognition, or “recognition” (in Hart’s sense), but also axiological acceptance by the addressees.19
A perfect characterization of contemporary LP can be read in a paper by von Wright (1985, 380): «The term “legal positivism” embraces a variety of positions among which there is a family resemblance. A common feature of many members of the family is the idea of a sharp separation of Is and Ought. Another is the non-cognitivist view that norms are prescriptions and therefore neither true nor false. As a third we may count the view that norms are “posited”».
All such three features of contemporary LP are shared by LR (Bobbio 1965, 156), which combines an empiricist conception of legal cognition with a sceptical view on interpretation. LR is an openly positivistic view about the law. To be sure, not all positivist legal scholars are realists, but all realists are (“hard”) positivists.20
References
Austin, John, 1879, Lectures on Jurisprudence or The Philosophy of Positive Law, 4th ed. by R. Campbell, John Murray, London.
Baldassarre, Antonio, 2005, “Miseria del positivismo giuridico”, in AA. VV., Studi in onore di Gianni Ferrara, Giappichelli, Torino, 2005, vol. I, 201-216.
Bentham, Jeremy, 1789, An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation, ed. by J.H. Burns and H.L.A. Hart, Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1996.
Bobbio, Norberto, 1961, Il positivismo giuridico, reprinted Giappichelli, Torino, 1966.
____________, 1963, Locke e il diritto naturale, reprinted Giappichelli, Torino, 2017.
____________, 1965, Giusnaturalismo e positivismo giuridico, Comunità, Milano.
____________, 1966, “Intervento”, in Tavola rotonda sul positivismo giuridico, Quaderni della rivista Il politico, Giuffré, Milano, 69-73.
____________, 1970a, “’Sein’ and ‘Sollen’ in Legal Science”, Archivfür Rechts- und Sozialphilosophie, LVI, 7-29.
____________, 1970b, Studi per una teoria generale del diritto, Giappichelli, Torino, new impression 2012.
Bulygin, Eugenio, 2006, El positivismo jurídico, Cátedra Ernesto Garzón Valdés, Fontamara, México.
Carcaterra, Gaetano, 1984, Il principio di normatività. Riflessioni sul normativismo, Bulzoni, Roma.
Chiassoni, Pierluigi, 2012, “Il realismo radicale della teoria pura del diritto”, Materiali per una storia della cultura giuridica, XLII, 237-261.
____________, 2013a, Positivismo giuridico. Una investigazione analitica, Mucchi, Modena.
____________, 2013b, “Wiener Realism”, in Luis Duarte d’Almeida, John Gardner, Leslie Green (eds.), Kelsen Revisited: New Essays on the Pure Theory of Law., Oxford/Hart Publishing, Portland/Oregon, 2013, 131-162.
____________, 2016, El discreto placer del positivismo jurídico, Universidad Externado de Colombia, Bogotá.
Comanducci, Paolo, 2009, “Constitucionalización y neoconstitucionalismo”, in Paolo Comanducci, Marian Ahumada Ruiz, Daniel González Lagier (eds.), Positivismo jurídico y neoconstitucionalismo, Fundación Coloquio Jurídico Europeo, Madrid.
____________, 2010, Hacia una teoría analítica del Derecho. Ensayos escogidos, Centro de Estudios Políticos y Constitucionales, Madrid.
Eng, Svein, 2011, “Lost in the System or Lost in Translation? The Exchanges between Hart and Ross”, Ratio Juris, XXIV, 194-246.
Grzegorczyk, Christophe, Michaut, Françoise, Troper, Michel (eds.), 1992, Le positivisme juridique, L.G.D.J., Paris.
Guastini, Riccardo, 2011, “Rule-Scepticism Restated”, in Leslie Green, Brian Leiter (eds.), Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Law, vol. 1, Oxford U.P., Oxford, 138-161.
Hägerström, Axel, 1953, Inquiries into the Nature of Law and Morals, ed. by K. Olivecrona, Almqvist and Wiksell, Stockholm.
Hart, H.L.A., 1958 "Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals”, Harvard Law Review, Vol. LXXI, 4, 593-629, reprinted in Hart 1983, 49-87.
____________, 1959, “Scandinavian Realism”, reprinted in Hart 1983, 161-169.
____________, 1983, Essays in Jurisprudence and Philosophy, Clarendon, Oxford.
Holtermann, Jakob v. H., 2017, “A Straw Man Revisited: Resettling the Score Between H.L.A. Hart and Scandinavian Legal Realism”, Santa Clara Law Review, 57, 1-42.
Jiménez Cano, Roberto Marino, 2008, Una metateoría del positivismo jurídico, Marcial Pons, Madrid.
Jori, Mario, 1987, Il giuspositivismo analitico italiano prima e dopo la crisi, Giuffré, Milano.
Kelsen, Hans, 1934, Introduction to the Problems of Legal Theory, ed. by Bonnie Litschewski Paulson and Stanley L. Paulson, Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1992.
____________, 1945, General Theory of Law and State, Harvard U. P., Cambridge (Mass.).
____________, 1965, “Law and Logic”, trans. P. Heath, in Hans Kelsen, Essays in Legal and Moral Philosophy, ed. Ota Weinberger, Dordrecht, Reidel, 1973, 228-253.
Leiter, Brian, 2007, Naturalizing Jurisprudence. Essays on American Legal Realism and Naturalism in Legal Philosophy, Oxford U.P., Oxford.
Matteucci, Nicola, 1963, “Positivismo giuridico e costituzionalismo”, Rivista trimestrale di diritto e procedura civile, XVII, 985-1100 (reprinted as a book: Il Mulino, Bologna, 1996).
Millard, Eric, 2008, “Positivisme logique et réalisme juridique”, Analisi e diritto, 177-189.
Modugno, Franco, 2008, Scritti sull’interpretazione costituzionale, ESI, Napoli.
Olivecrona, Karl, 1971, Law as Fact, Stevens & Sons, London.
Pattaro, Enrico, 1966, “Validità o verificabilità del diritto?”, Rivista trimestrale di diritto e procedura civile, 1966, 1005-1056.
____________, 1971, “Il realismo giuridico come alternativa al positivismo giuridico”, Rivista internazionale di filosofia del diritto, I, 61-126.
____________, 1972, “Il positivismo giuridico italiano dalla rinascita alla crisi”, reprinted in Uberto Scarpelli 1976, 451-487.
____________, 1982, “Per una critica della dottrina pura”, in Enrico Pattaro (ed.), Contributi al realismo giuridico, Giuffré, Milano, vol. 1, IX-LXXXVI.
____________, 1984, “La realtà del diritto e la sua conoscenza”, in Antonio Tarantino (ed.), Scienza e politica nel pensiero di Alf Ross, Giuffré, Milano, 103–146.
____________, 2018, “Girovagando… e discutendo”, Materiali per una storia del pensiero giuridico, I, 247-260.
Ross, Alf, 1958, On Law and Justice, Stevens & Sons, London.
____________, 1961, “Validity and the Conflict between Legal Positivism and Natural Law”, reprinted in Stanley L. Paulson and Bonnie Litschewski Paulson (eds.), Normativity and Norms. Critical Perspectives on Kelsenian Themes, Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1998, 147-163.
____________, 1962, “Review of H.L.A. Hart’s The Concept of Law”, The Yale Law Journal, LXXI, 1185-1190.
____________, 1965, Diritto e giustizia, trans. Giacomo Gavazzi, Einaudi, Torino.
____________, 1968, Directives and Norms, Routledge, London.
____________, 1997,Sobre el derecho y la justicia, trad. Genaro R. Carrió, Eudeba, Buenos Aires, 2nd ed.
Ruiz Manero, Juan, 2015, “Bobbio y el positivismo”, Revus, 26, 13-18.
Scarpelli, Uberto, 1965, Cos’è il positivismo giuridico, Comunità, Milano; new impression, ed. by A. Catania and M. Jori, Edizioni scientifiche italiane, Napoli, 1997.
____________, (ed.), 1976, Diritto e analisi del linguaggio, Comunità, Milano.
____________, 1984, “Auctoritas non veritas facit legem”, Rivista di filosofia, LXXV, 29-44.
____________, 1989, “Il positivismo giuridico rivisitato”, Rivista di filosofia, 461-476.
Troper, Michel, 1994, Pour une théorie juridique de l’État, PUF, Paris.
____________, 2001, La théorie du droit, le droit, l’État, PUF, Paris.
von Wright, Georg H. (1985), “Is and Ought”, in Stanley L. Paulson and Bonnie Litschewski Paulson (eds.), Normativity and Norms. Critical Perspectives on Kelsenian Themes, Clarendon, Oxford, 1999, 365-382.
Zagrebelsky, Gustavo, 1992, Il diritto mite, Einaudi, Torino.
____________, 2008, La legge e la sua giustizia, Il Mulino, Bologna.
Téléchargements
Publiée
Comment citer
Numéro
Rubrique
Licence
Ce travail est disponible sous licence Creative Commons Attribution - Pas d'Utilisation Commerciale - Pas de Modification 4.0 International.
ITAM, responsable de la publicación de la Revista, tiene los derechos de autor sobre los artículos publicados y el resto de las contribuciones. Las publicaciones están en acceso abierto y bajo una licencia de Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 International License. Esto significa, entre otras cosas, que los autores pueden compartir libremente sus artículos, una vez publicados en Isonomía, en sus páginas web personales, Academia.edu, etc. Entre la aceptación formal y la publicación en línea, los autores pueden compartir los borradores finales de sus artículos. En cambio, los autores deben pedir permiso para reproducir o reimprimir el trabajo, y mencionar, en la primera nota a pie de página, "publicado previamente en Isonomía, año, n. x, pp. xx-xx".